A SHORT HISTORY
OF UNBELIEF
CHAPTER TWO
God reveals Himself in the world which He has made, in the holy Scriptures and
in the Gospel of Jesus Christ His Son. In this three-fold way God reveals not
merely information about Himself but HIMSELF. But if God reveals Himself so
openly and plainly as this why are there so few that know Him? Why is His very
existence denied and ignored by so many? The Bible gives us the answer to this
question. It tells us that this prevailing ignorance concerning God is because
of sin and the blinding power of Satan. If our Gospel be hid, it is hid to them
that are lost, in whom the god of this world hath blinded the minds of them
which believe not, lest the light of the glorious Gospel of Christ, who is the
image of God, should shine unto them (2 Cor. 4:3-4).
In this present chapter we shall endeavor to give a short history of this
satanic blindness of unbelief from earliest times down to the present day and
show how it has affected the textual criticism of the Bible.
1. Ancient Forms Of Unbelief
Under ancient forms of unbelief we include heathenism and the various
philosophies that developed out of heathenism. These age-old errors may
fittingly be called unbelief because they all involve the denial of God the
Creator as He reveals Himself in the world which He has made.
1. False Sacrifices and the Growth of Heathenism
Heathenism (the worship of many gods and idols) began as a satanic perversion of
the divine ordinance of animal sacrifice. The Scriptures tell us that not long
after the first sin of Adam and Eve Abel, their younger son, began to offer up
animal sacrifices unto God. And this he did with God's approval as a sign and
pledge of his faith in Christ, the promised Redeemer (Heb. 11:4). But Adam's
elder son, Cain, was seduced by the devil (John 8:44) to offer God false,
unbloody sacrifices and then, when they were not approved, to slay his brother
Abel in a fit of jealous rage. And this sin, the Bible seems to indicate, was
the beginning of a false sacrificial system which was continued among the
descendants of Cain until the Flood, introduced again after the Flood by Noah's
unbelieving son Ham, and then carried to the ends of the earth when the nations
were scattered at Babel. At the instigation of the devil (Deut. 32:17; Ps.
106:37) in every land these heathen nations offered sacrifices and worship to
the forces of nature, to spirits, to the souls of the dead, and even to birds
and beasts and creeping things (Rom. 1:23).
In order to justify their false religious practices these heathen nations
rejected God's revelation of Himself in nature and substituted all manner of
foolish myths and absurd cosmogonies. The Hindus, for example, posited a golden
egg as the source of this present world. (1) The early Greeks also derived the
universe from a similar cosmic egg which was split in two, one half constituting
the heavens and the other the earth. (2) And according to the Babylonian
creation saga, the god Marduk constructed heaven and earth with the two halves
of the monster Tiamet after he had killed her and mutilated her body. (3) It is
to absurdities such as these that Paul refers in the passage just mentioned.
Because that when they knew God, they glorified Him not as God, neither were
thankful; but became vain in their imaginations, and their foolish heart was
darkened (Rom. 1:21).
But although the heathen had rejected the true God, they could not escape the
accusation of their consciences (Rom. 2:15) and the fundamental realities of the
spiritual world. Studies in comparative religion indicate that in heathenism
there were three areas of major concern. First, there was the menace of hostile
spiritual powers. Demons were feared the world over, and charms and incantations
were devised to ward off their malignant influences. In Babylonia especially
these counter-measures were erected into a pseudoscience. (4) Second, there was
the mystery of the after-life and the problem of providing for its needs. Some
of the most characteristic features of Egyptian civilization stem from this
interest. The embalming, the mummifying, the pyramids in which the dead kings
were buried, all these were part of the care bestowed upon the dead. Third,
there was anxiety over the judgment after death and the consequences of this
great assize. In texts written on the inside of coffins and in inscriptions
found in pyramids the Egyptians recorded their conceptions of the rewards and
punishments which await men in the next world. (5) Similarly the Greek Orphic
literature abounds in descriptions of fearful torments visited upon the wicked
after death. (6)
In these heathen thought-ways there was undoubtedly much that was absurd. But,
on the whole, the thinking of these ancient heathen was not nearly so foolish as
that of modern materialists who derive mind from matter, who deny that there is
any essential difference between right and wrong, and who have generated the
present tidal crime-wave by their insanely obstinate contention that no one
ought to be punished for anything he does but merely "rehabilitated." The
heathen were more realistic than these modern unbelievers because they perceived
that mind is spirit and that they themselves were spirits as far as their minds
were concerned. From this they went on to reason, quite correctly, that there
must be other spirits and that some of these spirits must be evil, seeing that
there is evil in the world. They saw also that wrong must be avenged and that
therefore there must be judgment and penalties after death.
At a much later date these ideas were developed by the Persian thinker Zoroaster
(c. 650 B.C.) into an ethical dualism in which two uncreated beings strove
together in perpetual conflict. One of these was the good god Ahura Mazda, the
other the evil god Angra Mainyu. (7) It is probable, however, that Zoroaster
borrowed from the revealed religion of the Israelites and especially from the
biblical teaching concerning Satan, "the Adversary." We read in II Kings 17:6
that before the birth of Zoroaster captive Israelites were settled in the
territory of the Medes and Persians, and it may be from them that Zoroaster
obtained some of his conceptions.
2. Eastern Philosophy—The Transmigration of Souls. Ancestor Worship
Belief in the transmigration of souls has in all ages been a common feature of
heathenism everywhere. This is the theory that after death the soul is reborn
into another body, a notion which has dominated the thinking of hundreds of
millions of Asiatics ever since it made its appearance in India some time after
1000 B. C. Hinduism and Buddhism are built upon it. Both these religions
presuppose that man is caught in an eternally revolving wheel of birth and
death, an endless series of reincarnations. How can a man escape this ceaseless
cycle of rebirths? Two answers were given to this question.
The Hindus sought relief through the absorption of the human soul (atman) into
the world-soul, which they called "the self-existent Brahman." This Brahman they
regarded as the only reality. The material world which can be seen and touched
was only an appearance. It was maya (illusion). By spiritual disciplines and
ascetic practices it was possible for an earnest seeker to arrive at the insight
that his individual soul (atman) was one with the world-soul (Brahman). When
this mystic knowledge was attained, the cycle of rebirths came to an end. (8)
Buddha (557-477 B.C.), on the other hand, taught that salvation came only
through the extinction of the human soul. Strictly speaking, he even denied that
there was such a thing as a soul. He believed only in a succession of rebirths.
Each existence depended on a previous existence just as one lamp is lighted from
another. To terminate this cycle Buddha offered his famous eight-fold path.
Those that followed this program would extinguish their desire for life and
enter into Nirvana, a word which means literally, "blowing out the light." (9)
In China the two great molders of thought were Lao-tse (b. 604 B.C.) and
Confucius (551-478 B.C.). Lao-tse was the founder of the Taoist system, the only
native Chinese philosophy. He emphasized tao, the way of nature. He regarded the
operations of nature as effortless and purposeless. The wise man therefore must
conform to nature by living an effortless and quiet life. (10) Confucius, on the
other hand was unphilosophic, occupying himself entirely with religious
ceremonies and ethics. Filial piety was the essence of his ethical system. A son
who respects and obeys his father will be a kind brother, sincere friend, and
loyal subject. (11) The religion of China, however, antedates these two sages by
many centuries and may be defined as a union of nature worship and ancestor
worship, a mixture which encouraged the veneration of spirits of every kind.
(12) It is probable that the great bulk of the Chinese people still continue in
bondage to spirit worship despite the efforts of the present communist regime to
replace this ancient superstition with the materialistic atheism of modern
unbelief.
3. The Greek Philosophy —Materialism and Idealism
In contrast with Eastern thinkers, the early Greek philosophers were chiefly
concerned with the external world, and this they interpreted in a materialistic
way. Even God they regarded as in some sense material. According to Thales (c.
600 B.C. ), water was the basic constituent of the universe. To this underlying
cosmic fluid he attributed a certain divinity, declaring that "all things are
full of gods.'' (13) Anaximander (611-545 B.C.) believed that the universal was
an infinite (boundless) something which was "immortal and indestructible,
unbegotten and incorruptible." This boundless substance controlled the motion of
all things, and in this sense Aneximander called it "the deity.'' (14)
Anaximenes (d. 499 B.C.) regarded air as the basic substance underlying all
things, and this air he spoke of as a "god." (15) Heracleitus (540-480 B.C.)
assigned the primary place in the universe to fire, which he thought of as the
universal reason (logos). (16) And two hundred years later this theory was
revived by the Stoics, who also made fire the fundamental element and regarded
it as the creative world-reason (logos spermatikos). (17)
These materialistic hypotheses led to the conclusion that nothing in the
universe was permanent, since water, air, and fire were all subject to change.
This meant, as Protagoras (c. 450 B.C. ) and other critics pointed out, that
there was no possibility of permanent truth. (18) It was to combat such
skepticism as this that the later Greek thinkers developed their idealistic
philosophies. These idealists divided the universe into two worlds, the world of
matter which was always changing and the world of ideas which never changed.
There was a difference of opinion, however, as to what these unchangeable ideas
were. The Pythagoreans (c. 450 B.C.) thought of them as mathematical ideas. (19)
Socrates (470-399 B.C.) gave them an ethical connotation. (20) According to
Plato (427-347 B.C.), these ideas were all summed up and included in the Idea of
the Good, the supreme and immutable purpose of the universe. Late in life Plato
added the concept of the World-Builder (Demiurge) that molds and shapes the
world of matter, using the Idea of the Good as a pattern. Because of this many
scholars have claimed that Plato believed in a personal God. But Plato himself
warned that he was speaking mythically. It is probable therefore that Plato's
World-Builder is merely a personification of his Idea of the Good, introduced by
him to bridge the gap between the world of ideas and the world of matter and
thus to provide a place in his philosophy for the physical sciences. (21)
(d) The Philosophy of Aristotle
Aristotle (384-322 B.C.), Plato's most famous disciple, developed a philosophy
which attempted to be neither idealism nor materialism but a fusion of these two
tendencies. According to Aristotle, matter is mere possibility and ideas are the
forms that limit and guide this possibility. Matter, he taught, never exists by
itself but only in union with these forms that limit and guide it. Perhaps a
reference to a children's guessing game may serve to illustrate these basic
tenets of Aristotle's philosophic system. One child says, "I am thinking of
something." Then the other child tries to determine what it is by a series of
questions. "Is it alive? Is it an animal? Is it a vertebrate? Is it a mammal? Is
it a meat-eating mammal? Is it a dog? Is it our dog Fido?" The something of
which the first child is thinking represents Aristotle's matter. At first it has
the possibility of being almost anything, but then it is limited successively by
the second child's questions, which represent Aristotle's forms, until finally
it takes definite shape as the individual, existing dog Fido. In some such way,
according to Aristotle, the forms limit matter, dividing it into classes and
sub-classes, until finally individual organisms are arrived at and brought into
existence.
Thus Aristotle viewed the world as an eternal process. Always the forms are
limiting matter, dividing it into classes, sub-classes, and finally individual
organisms. Always matter is moving up through the forms until these individual
organisms are brought into existence. Always these organisms are growing to
maturity and passing away only to be succeeded by new organisms of the same sort
which in their turn are produced by this same union of matter and form. Hence
for Aristotle God was not the Creator who brought the universe into being out of
nothing at a definite time. Like Plato, Aristotle conceived of God as merely the
highest form or idea. According to Aristotle, God moves the world by being "the
object of the world's desire." Matter moves up toward God through its union with
the forms. In this Aristotle differed from Plato, who connected ideas and matter
by having the World-Builder (Demiurge) come down to the world of matter from the
world of ideas. (22)
2. Philosophy In The Early And Medieval Church
Beware lest any man spoil you through philosophy and vain deceit, after the
tradition of men, after the rudiments of the world and not after Christ (Col.
2:8). Here Paul warns against the ever present danger of corrupting the truth of
God with the false philosophies of unbelieving men, and even a brief survey of
the impact of Greek philosophy upon the early and medieval Church shows how much
this warning was needed.
(a) Philosophy in the Early Church
From the second century B.C. onward the influences of Greek philosophy were at
work among the Jews, especially those that dwelt at Alexandria in Egypt. Here
the renowned Jewish thinker Philo (20 B.C. - 42 A.D.) constructed a philosophic
system which attempted to combine the teaching of the Old Testament with the
theories of Plato and the logos doctrine of Heracleitus and the Stoics. It was
in this last direction particularly that he sought a link between Greek
philosophy and the sacred Hebrew Scriptures. The ancient Greek version of the
Old Testament (the Septuagint) used the term logos to translate the Hebrew term
dabar (word). Philo interpreted these biblical passages in a Greek sense.
According to Philo, they refer to the Logos, the highest of all divine forces
and the means by which God created the world, not out of nothing as the Bible
teaches but in Greek fashion out of already existing substance. The Logos was
employed by God to do this work because, Philo maintained, God Himself was too
exalted to bring Himself into contact with defiling matter. (23)
The influences of Greek thought can be seen also in many of the heresies which
plagued the Church in the early Christian centuries. One of the earliest of
these was Gnosticism, which flourished around 150 A.D. Enlarging on the concepts
of Plato and Philo, the Gnostics placed between the highest God and the world of
matter many Eons or beings, including not only the Demiurge and the Logos but
also Christ and Jesus, who were regarded as two separate entities. Other
heretical views of the incarnation in the early Church are as follows: docetism,
the theory that Christ's human nature was not real but merely an appearance;
adoptionism, the assertion that Jesus was born a mere man and then became the
Son of God through the indwelling of the Logos and the descent of the Holy
Spirit upon Him at baptism; Sabellianism, the teaching of Sabellius (220 A.D. )
that the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit are merely three ways in which God
has revealed Himself. And finally, these false doctrines culminated in the
greatest heresy of all, namely, the contention of Arius (318 A.D.) that before
the foundation of the world God the Father had created the Son out of nothing.
(24)
Amid this welter of heretical teaching there was danger that the orthodox
Christian faith would perish, but in the sacred Scriptures and especially in the
Gospel of John God had provided the remedy for this perilous situation. Writing
under the inspiration of the Holy Spirit, this "beloved disciple" had expounded
the true meaning of the Hebrew term dabar and the Greek term logos. In the
beginning was the Word and the Word was with God, and the Word was God (John
1:1). The reference was to Christ the eternal Son of God. He is the Word, the
light of men (John 1:4), who was made flesh and revealed His glory (John 1:14).
Guided therefore by these teachings d the New Testament Scriptures, the Church
was able to formulate at Nicaea (324 A.D.) and at Chalcedon (451 A.D.) the true
doctrine of the holy Trinity and of the incarnation of Christ. Three Persons,
Father, Son and Holy Ghost, but one God. Two natures, divine and human, but one
Person. (25)
(b) Doctrinal Decline—Priestcraft, Image Worship, the Papacy
The triumphs of the Christian faith at Nicaea and Chalcedon were followed by a
long period of doctrinal decline in which errors of every sort multiplied and
entrenched themselves. The power of the priesthood and the papacy steadily
increased as the New Testament doctrine of the universal priesthood of believers
was more and more forgotten. Out of veneration for the martyrs and their relics
grew the worship of innumerable saints and images. The spread of monasticism
induced thousands of misguided souls to renounce the world and in the shelter of
cloisters and convents to seek to please God with all manner of ascetic
practices and man-made disciplines. The saints who lived in this monastic way
were thought to have done more than the law of God required and thus to have
laid up extra credits with God. Drawing on these extra credits (the Treasury of
merit), the popes claimed the power to sell Indulgences to less perfect
Christians, shortening or remitting altogether their punishment in purgatory
after death. Thus Christianity, a religion of God's free grace, had been
transformed almost entirely into a religion of works. (26)
(c) The Rise and Progress of Mohammedanism
Mohammedanism is the earliest and largest of the cults which have followed in
the wake of Christianity. Its founder Mohammed ( 570-632 A.D. ), like many other
false teachers, claimed to be the Comforter Whom Jesus had promised His
disciples (John 14:26). He made this identification by changing the Greek word
Paracletos (Comforter) to Periclytos (Illustrious) and then equating it with his
own name Ahmed, which also meant Illustrious. (27) He also claimed that the
religion which he preached was not younger but actually older than either
Judaism or Christianity, being a restoration of the original religion of Abraham
and Ishmael. Mohammed called his religion Islam (surrender). Believers were to
surrender to the will of God just as Abraham did when he was willing to
sacrifice his son Isaac. They were also to renounce all idols and believe in one
God just as Abraham (according to tradition) renounced the idols of his father
Terah (Azer). Other religious duties were to pray five times a day, to give
alms, to fast during the daylight hours in the month Ramadan (in which the Koran
had been revealed), and to make at least one pilgrimage to Mecca.
Mohammed proclaimed himself "the messenger of Allah and the seal of the
prophets," in other words, the last and greatest of them. Among the prophets
whom he claimed to supersede he included most of the outstanding biblical
characters, for example, Noah, Abraham, Ishmael, Isaac, Jacob, Moses, Solomon,
John the Baptist, and Jesus. He acknowledged the virgin birth of Jesus but
denied His deity. "The Messiah, Jesus son of Mary, was only a messenger of
Allah. Allah is but one God. Far be it from Him that He should have a son." (28)
Instead Mohammed deified his Koran which, he maintained, confirmed and
superseded the Law and the Gospel that had been revealed to Moses and Jesus
respectively. According to Mohammed, the Koran was a hidden, heavenly book which
had been sent down to the earthly plane on a certain night of the month Ramadan.
Beginning with that night, Mohammed claimed, the angel Gabriel read to him at
intervals out of the Koran, one section at a time. As each portion of the Koran
was made known to him, Mohammed would go forth and recite it to the people. They
in turn would either write it down or commit it to memory, and from these
written and oral sources the present Koran was compiled soon after Mohammed's
death by the caliphs Abu Bakr and Othman. (29)
Orthodox Mohammedans (Sonnites) believe that the Koran is eternal and uncreated,
subsisting in the very essence of God. According to them, Mohammed himself held
this same view and called anyone who denied it an infidel. In spite of this,
however, there have been Mohammedan sects that have disputed this doctrine,
especially the Motazalites who very rightly pointed out that this deification of
the Koran involved the belief in two eternal beings and thus denied the unity of
God. (30) This controversy shows us clearly that the Mohammedan doctrine of
Scripture is only a crude caricature of the true, trinitarian, Christian
doctrine. The Scriptures of the Old and New Testaments are eternal (Psalm
119:89) but not as an uncreated, eternal book. They are eternal in the same
sense that God's decrees are eternal. They are the product of God's eternal act.
They are the words of eternal life (John 6:68) which God the Father gave to
Jesus Christ His Son in the eternal Covenant of Grace for the salvation of
sinners. For I have given unto them the words which Thou gayest Me (John 17:8).
For more than one thousand years Mohammedanism was the chief external foe of
Christianity. The death of Mohammed was succeeded by a century of conquest in
which Syria, Egypt, North Africa and Spain speedily passed into the possession
of his followers. Turned back at Tours by Charles Martel in 732, the Mohammedan
menace remained quiescent for seven hundred years and then flared up again with
renewed intensity after the capture of Constantinople in 1453 by the Turks.
Under Suleyman the Magnificent (r. 1520-1566) Turkish power extended deep into
central Europe and dominated the Mediterraneen. It was not until the Turks were
defeated in the great naval battle of Lepanto in 1571 that the tide began to
turn against them.
These Mohammedan conquests, tragic though they were, clearly reveal the guiding
hand of God's providence. In the first place, they served to isolate and
preserve the True New Testament Text until the time came for its transferal to
Western Europe. In the second place, by diverting the attention of the Roman
Catholic powers during the first critical years of the Reformation they helped
to save Protestantism from annihilation. And finally, it is possible that
through these conquests the way has been prepared for the fulfillment of
biblical prophecy. Perhaps the coming national conversion of the Jews will
include their Mohammedan neighbors, these sons of Ishmael who like unbelieving
Israel are children of Abraham after the flesh but not after the Spirit. It may
be that thus will be brought to pass the saying of Isaiah. In that day shall
Israel be the third with Egypt and with Assyria, even a blessing in the midst of
the land. Whom the LORD of hosts shall bless, saying, Blessed be Egypt My
people, and Assyria the work of My hands, and Israel Mine inheritance (Isaiah
19:24-25).
(d) The Scholastic Philosophy—Faith and Reason
During the middle-ages the study of Aristotle's philosophy flourished greatly,
at first among the Nestorians in Syria, then among the Mohammedans, then among
the Jews, (31) and finally in the educational centers of Western Europe, where
it developed into the Scholastic Philosophy. This was the attempt to harmonize
the dogmas of the Roman Catholic Church with the teachings of Aristotle, an
effort which placed new emphasis on the relation of faith to reason.
The prevailing tendency of scholasticism was to make reason and faith
independent of each other, the former ruling in the realm of nature, the latter
in the realm of grace. It became customary to say that Aristotle was Christ's
forerunner in things pertaining to nature and John the Baptist in things
pertaining to grace. The schoolmen differed, however, as to the degree of
separation existing between reason and faith. Albertus Magnus (1193-1280) denied
that there was any real contradiction between faith and reason. Faith, he
insisted, was not contrary to reason but above it. All the dogmas of Roman
Catholicism, he maintained, either agreed with the philosophy of Aristotle or at
least could not be proved false on Aristotelian grounds. Duns Scotus (d. 1308),
on the other hand, admitted that the Roman Catholic dogmas were contrary to the
philosophy of Aristotle but held that these dogmas should be believed in anyway
on the authority of the Roman Catholic Church. In such cases Duns operated with
two levels of truth. What was false on the level of reason was true on the level
of faith. (32)
Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274) used Aristotle's philosophy as a foundation for the
Roman Catholic religion of works. As has been stated, Aristotle taught that God
moves the world by being "the object of the world's desire" and that matter
moves up toward God through its union with the forms. Thomas applied this
Aristotelian concept to the moral realm. Man strives for the highest end, and
the highest end of all is to gain a knowledge or vision of God. Man attains this
end through meritorious deeds and through the grace supplied by the sacraments
of the Church. Thus not only in a physical sense but also in a spiritual way man
moves upward in the scale of being toward God, the object of his soul's desire.
(33) This is somewhat similar to the modern theory of theistic evolution, and
many Roman Catholics today are attempting to bring Aquinas up to date by
substituting evolutionism for Aristotelianism as the philosophic element in his
system.
In philosophy and science, therefore, Roman Catholicism has followed its usual
procedure of absorbing non-Christian elements rather than rejecting and refuting
them. And the same has always been true in the political and ecclesiastical
spheres. Today, for example, the Church of Rome is trying hard to draw Greek
Catholics, Protestants, socialists, and even communists under its mantle in
order that through the addition of these groups its ecumenical organization may
become all-powerful. Hence the Roman Catholic conception of faith has always
been that of blind obedience, the promise to believe whatever the Roman pontiff
at any given moment officially decides must be believed.
In order, then, to understand the relationship of faith to reason we must first
of all take a biblical view of our faith. If I really believe in God, then God
is real to me, more real to me even than my faith in Him. For if it is the other
way round, if my faith in God is more real to me than God Himself, then I am not
believing but doubting. Hence in thinking about our faith and in describing it
to others we must begin with that which is most real, namely, God. We must
confess that God is, that He reveals Himself in the world, in the Scriptures,
and in the Gospel of Christ, and that our faith in Him and in Jesus Christ His
Son is not the product of our sinful, human minds and wills but the gracious
gift of His Holy Spirit (Eph. 2:8). In this book, therefore, we are striving to
present only this biblical and consistent view of Christian faith. This is why
we defend the Traditional New Testament Text, the Textus Receptus, and the King
James Version. In them God draws nigh and reveals himself.
After we take a biblical view of faith, we are then able to take a biblical view
of reason and of its relationship to faith. Reason is the mental faculty by
which we know the facts, the temporal truths which God establishes through His
works of creation and providence. Faith is the spiritual faculty by which,
through the power of the Holy Spirit, we lay hold on God Himself, the Supreme
Truth, as He reveals Himself in and through the facts. Hence faith is not a
"super-added" gift, as many of the medieval schoolmen supposed, not reason's cap
and crown, but its foundation. We defend the Christian faith by showing that it
is the only foundation on which the facts can be arranged and that all the
attempts of unbelievers to substitute other foundations result only in confusion
and chaos. For other foundation can no man lay than that is laid which is Jesus
Christ (I Cor. 3:11)
Anselm (1033-1109), the "father of scholastic philosophy," was emphatic in his
insistence on faith as the foundation of reason and knowledge. "I believe," he
declared, "in order that I may understand. (34) But this biblical emphasis on
the priority of faith did not long continue. For one thing, Anselm himself lost
sight of it in his famous "ontological" argument for the existence of God.
Taking a neutral view of his idea of God, he first regarded it as merely a part
of his mental experience and then attempted to prove that it was a necessarily
true idea. And in Anselm's successors, as we have seen, the Roman Catholic
conception of faith as submission to ecclesiastical authority tended inevitably
to place faith and reason in separate spheres.
Hence it was not until the Protestant Reformation that the reconciliation of
faith and reason became possible. Then it was that believing scholars and
theologians began to describe their faith consistently, taking as their starting
point that which is most real to every true believer, namely, God, who reveals
Himself in the world, in the Scriptures, and in the Gospel of Christ. Such a
description opens the way to a better understanding of the intellectual
implications of our Christian faith. We see that we are not only justified by
faith but renewed in knowledge (Col. 3:10). By faith we lay hold on Christ,
reason's only true and sure foundation. And we know that the Son of God is come,
and hath given us an understanding, that we may know Him that is true, and we
are in Him that is true, even in His Son Jesus Christ. This is the true God, and
eternal life (I John 5:20).
3. Revelation And The Protestant Reformation
What does God reveal in the word which He has created, in the holy Scriptures,
and in the Gospel of Christ? Does He reveal Himself, or does He merely reveal
information concerning Himself? This is a question of deepest interest to every
earnest Christian. For if in nature, in the Scriptures, and in the Gospel of
Christ God didn't reveal Himself but only information concerning Himself, our
Christian faith would never bring us near to God. We would know certain facts
about God, but we would not know God. We would believe in certain doctrines
about Christ, but we would not believe in Christ as a Person. But thanks be to
God that this is not the case. For the Bible itself teaches us that God's
revelation is a revelation of HIMSELF, not of mere information concerning
Himself.
(a) The Protestant Reformers and the Living Word of God
God reveals HIMSELF, not mere information concerning Himself. The Protestant
Reformers understood this fact. To them the Bible was no mere book of doctrine
but the revelation of the living God. In the Bible Christ revealed Himself.
Martin Luther emphasized this in the preface of his German New Testament version
(1522). "Briefly, St John's Gospel and his first Epistle, St. Paul's Epistles,
especially those to the Romans, Galatians, Ephesians, and St. Peter's First
Epistle: these are the books which shew thee Christ and teach all which it is
needful and blessed for thee to know, even if you never see nor hear any other
book or any other doctrine." (35)
It is true that Luther in his zeal pushed this principle too far, even to the
point of making some unfavorable remarks concerning Hebrews, James, Jude and
Revelation, alleging that these New Testament books did not present Christ
clearly enough. But these were mere hasty criticisms which had no permanent
effect on the development of Lutheran doctrine. Under the guidance of the Holy
Spirit Lutheran churches soon united in confessing their faith in the canonical
Scriptures of the Old and New Testaments "as the only judge, norm, and rule,
according to which, as by the only touchstone, all doctrines are to be
examined." (The Formula of Concord, 1576) (36)
John Calvin also regarded God's revelation of Himself as a present reality which
ought to guide and govern the whole of human life. This was the theme of the
opening chapters of his Institutes, namely, God's revelation of Himself in
nature, the clarification and amplification of this revelation in the
Scriptures, and the certification and confirmation of this revelation by the
testimony of the Holy Spirit in the hearts of believers. And in the French
Confession (1559) Calvin and his followers gave a finished statement of their
faith in the books of holy Scripture. "We know these books to be canonical, and
the sure rule of our faith, not so much by the common accord and consent of the
Church, as by the testimony and inward illumination of the Holy Spirit, which
enables us to distinguish them from other ecclesiastical books upon which,
however useful, we can not found any articles of faith." (37)
(b) The Thirty Nine Articles and the Westminster Confession
The official position of the Church of England (Episcopal Church), as defined in
the Thirty Nine Articles (1562), was in agreement with the Protestant Reformers
as far as the authority of the Bible was concerned. "Holy Scripture containeth
all things necessary to salvation: so that whatsoever is not read therein, nor
may be proved thereby, is not to be required of any man, that it should be
believed as an article of the Faith, or be thought requisite or necessary to
salvation. In the name of the Holy Scripture we do understand those canonical
Books of the Old and New Testament, of whose authority was never any doubt in
the Church." (38) This Article was included in the Methodist Articles of
Religion, an abridgement of the Thirty Nine Articles prepared by John Wesley and
adopted by American Methodists in 1784. (39)
The first chapter of the Westminster Confession is generally regarded as
containing the fullest exposition of the orthodox Protestant faith concerning
the holy Scriptures. The section on the testimony of the Holy Spirit is
especially notable and reads (substantially) as follows: "We may be moved and
induced by the testimony of the Church to an high and reverent esteem of the
holy Scripture; and the heavenliness of the matter, the efficacy of the
doctrine, the majesty of the style, the agreement of all the parts, the purpose
of the whole (which is to give all glory to God), the full explanation it makes
of the only way of man's salvation, the many other incomparable excellencies,
and the entire perfection of it, are arguments by which it abundantly proves
itself to be the Word of God. But our full persuasion and assurance of its
infallible truth and divine authority is from the inward work of the Holy
Spirit, bearing witness by and with the Word in our hearts." (40)
This Westminster Confession was adopted not only by Presbyterians (1647) but
also by Congregationalists (1658) (41) and by Baptists (1677). (42) Some parts
of the Confession were altered to agree with Congregational and Baptist
convictions, but in regard to the chapter on the Scriptures all three
denominations found themselves in complete accord.
(c) The Decline of Protestantism—Dead Orthodoxy, Pietism, Modernism
By the middle of the 17th century all the great Protestant creeds had been
formulated, but instead of going forward in the strength of this achievement
Protestantism entered soon after into a long process of decline which has
continued unto the present day in spite of intervening periods of revival and
missionary effort. One of the factors that brought about this decline was the
development of dead orthodoxy. Many orthodox Protestants came to regard
Christianity as mainly a system of doctrine set forth in a creed and confirmed
by proof-texts taken from the Bible. Hence the Gospel was preached and taught in
a cold, dead way merely as information concerning God and not as God's
revelation of Himself. The result of this emphasis was all too often a dead
faith, which, because it was centered on a creed and not on God Himself, soon
withered away and was replaced by various forms of unbelief and finally by
modernism.
The second factor in the decline of Protestantism was pietism. The pietists
endeavored to combat the evils of dead orthodoxy, but in their protest against
the misuse of creeds they went too far in the other direction. Their tendency
was to ignore creeds altogether and to emphasize the feelings at the expense of
the intellect. "Use your heart and not your head," was their slogan. The result
was an unthinking emotionalism which left the door open to many errors and
eventually to modernism.
God is truth. But He is also more than truth. He is a living Person. Therefore
divine revelation is more than a revelation of the truth concerning God. It is
this, but it is also more than this. It is God's revelation of Himself. In
nature, in the Scriptures, and in the Gospel of Christ God reveals HIMSELF. When
once we understand this and commit ourselves to God through Jesus Christ His
Son, then we cut off all occasion to dead orthodoxy and pietism and arm
ourselves to do battle against the modernism which results from these two
errors.
4. Modern Philosophy—The Neutral World-View
Modern philosophy made its appearance immediately after the Protestant
Reformation. The leaders of this new movement ridiculed both sides in the then
current religious controversy. "Once there was a man," they quipped, "who had
two sons, one Catholic and one Protestant. And so each brother converted the
other, and God had mercy on them both because of their zeal." But in order to
escape punishment these early modern philosophers denied that they were
antichristian. They were only being impartial, they insisted, and unprejudiced.
And from this claim has arisen the modern world-view, which has always pretended
to be neutral and unbiased in all religious matters.
Weakened by dead orthodoxy and pietism, conservative Protestants of the late
17th and 18th centuries failed to resist the rising neutral world-view as
vigorously as they should have done. Instead of taking their stand upon God's
revelation of Himself in holy Scripture and pointing out that the neutral
world-view is not really neutral but antichristian and full of contradictions,
they began to adopt it themselves, especially in those areas of thought not
specifically covered by their Reformation creeds, namely, philosophy and
biblical introduction and above all New Testament textual criticism. Soon a
serious inconsistency developed in the thinking of orthodox Protestants. At
their colleges and theological seminaries especially students and teachers alike
were torn between two world-views. In their study of systematic theology they
maintained the believing world-view of the Protestant Reformation, but in their
study of philosophy, biblical introduction, and New Testament textual criticism
they adopted the neutral world-view of Post-Reformation rationalism. Today this
illogical state of affairs is still being perpetuated in a few theological
schools, but most of them have resolved the tension by becoming completely
modernistic. The purpose of this book is to endeavor to reverse this trend by
promoting consistently Christian thought especially in the sphere of New
Testament textual criticism.
(a) Rationalistic Philosophy—Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz
The early modern philosophers were rationalists. They made reason (the thinking
mind) the starting point of their philosophical systems. And of these
rationalistic philosophers the very earliest was Rene Descartes (1596-1650), who
is usually considered the founder of modern philosophy. Descartes is famous for
his use of doubt as a philosophical method. (43) He began by doubting everything
that it was possible for him to doubt. He doubted not only the existence of God
but also the demonstrations of mathematics, the existence of the material world,
and even the existence of his own body. Finally, however, Descartes came to
something which he could not doubt, namely, the existence of his own mind. Even
while he was doubting, he was thinking. Hence he could not doubt that his mind
existed. "I think, therefore I am." This, he believed, was the rock-bottom
foundation of certainty on which he could build his philosophical system. (44)
After Descartes had established that it was impossible for him to doubt the
existence of his own mind, he reversed his reasoning. Discarding doubt as a
philosophical method, he endeavored to argue his way back to certainty, using as
stepping-stones the very convictions that he had previously doubted. He now
asserted that the existence of God was not doubtful after all, because the idea
of a perfect God which he had in his mind could not have come from an imperfect,
doubting being like himself but must have been created in his mind by a perfect
God. Therefore it must be that a perfect God exists and that the material world
exists. For surely a perfect God would not deceive him by causing him to think
that a material world existed if it did not in fact exist. (45)
But Descartes' attempt to regain his certainty through these arguments is very
illogical. For if it is actually possible to doubt the existence of God and the
material world and everything else except self-existence, then it is forever
impossible to be certain about anything except self-existence. Everything else,
having been doubted, must remain uncertain. Hence no Christian ought to adopt
Descartes' philosophy since it casts doubt on the existence of God.
Two other famous rationalistic philosophers were Baruch Spinoza (1632-1677) and
G. W. Leibniz (1646-1716). They believed that through the use of reason alone it
was possible to deduce the fundamental nature of God and the universe. Spinoza
was a pantheist. Indeed the term pantheism was invented to characterize his
philosophy. He believed that there was but one basic substance of which both God
and the universe were composed. According to Spinoza, God is nature viewed as
active (natura naturans), and the universe is nature viewed as passive (natura
naturata). (46)
Leibniz believed that the universe is composed of simple substances or souls,
which he called monads. In non-living matter the monads are unconscious, in a
stupor, so to speak. In animals the monads are conscious. In human beings the
monads are rational. As rational beings we acknowledge God as the sufficient
reason or cause of our existence. The monads have no communication with each
other but cooperate according to a harmony which has been pre-established by
God. (47)
(b) Empirical Philosophy—Locke, Berkeley. Hume
The above mentioned rationalistic philosophers (Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz)
conceived of thought as consisting chiefly of innate ideas which were implanted
in the human mind at birth and which developed as the human mind developed. The
philosophers whom we shall now consider were empiricists (from the Greek word
empeiria meaning experience). They denied the existence of innate ideas and
regarded thought as simply a series of mental experiences.
The first of these empirical philosophers was John Locke (1632-1704). (48) In
his famous Essay on Human Understanding (1690) he sought to demonstrate that the
ideas commonly thought to be innate were not really so since they were not found
in idiots or children or savages, a contention which modern investigation has
not substantiated. At birth, Locke asserted, the human mind is "white paper,
void of all characters, without any ideas". (49) He believed that ideas enter
the mind only through sensation (sense experience, e.g., seeing, touching,
hearing, etc.) or through reflection ("the notice which the mind takes of its
own operations and the manner of them"). (50) Hence, in his theory of knowledge,
Locke came perilously close to maintaining that the mind can know nothing else
than its own ideas. "Since the mind, in all its thoughts and reasonings, hath no
other immediate object but its own ideas, which it alone does or can
contemplate, it is evident that our knowledge is only conversant about them."
(51) Locke, however, was inconsistent and so declined to develop his philosophy
to the point of complete skepticism. He allowed the existence of the material
world as the source of sense experience and even insisted that we can be certain
of our own existence, of causation, and of the existence of God, conclusions
which by no means follow from the premises which he laid down.
George Berkeley (1685-1753) and David Hume (1711-1776) carried Locke's
principles to their logical conclusion. Berkeley, who later became Anglican
Bishop of Cloyne in southern Ireland, used Locke's philosophy as the basis of
his famous argument against materialism. He contended that only spirits and
ideas exist. Matter does not exist, he maintained, because we do not experience
matter but only our idea of matter. Hence matter is God's idea, and the creation
described in Genesis was not a creation of matter but only a creation of spirits
(angels and men) with whom God could share His idea of matter. (52)
Hume pushed on to other extreme positions. He denied not only the existence of
matter but also his own self-existence on the ground that he was not able to
experience his self but only his ideas. Likewise, he denied causation, asserting
that he could not experience it but only a succession of events in time. (53)
(c) Critical Philosophy—Immanuel Kant
The skepticism of David Hume concerning causation stimulated Immanuel Kant
(1724-1804), one of the world's most influential thinkers, to develop his
critical philosophy, an investigation of the powers and the limitations of the
human mind. (54)
In his Critique of Pure Reason (1781) and his Prolegomena (1783) Kant dealt with
the problem of human knowledge. (55) According to Kant, we cannot know things as
they are in themselves but only as they appear to us in our human experience.
Whenever our minds begin to speculate about things as they are in themselves
apart from our human experience of them, we run into antinomies
(contradictions). We find that there are two sides to each question. Arguments
of equal validity can be found to support either the thesis (affirmative) or the
antithesis (negative), so that we cannot determine which side to take. Hence we
can know nothing certain concerning things as they are in themselves. Certain
knowledge, Kant insisted, is confined to the realm of experience. Space, time
and causation are valid concepts because they are facts of our experience.
Such, in brief, was Kant's reply to Hume. But many subsequent philosophers have
denied that Kant really refuted Hume, because Kant simply assumed what Hume
denied, namely, that the human mind experiences causation. Also many subsequent
philosophers have accused Kant of inconsistency. He seems to imply that things
in themselves are causes of human experience, and this would make causation not
merely a fact of experience but also one of the things in themselves of which we
can know nothing certain.
In his Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals (1785) and his Critique of
Practical Reason (1788) Kant discussed the concepts God, freedom and immortality
and their relation to the moral law. (56) According to Kant, it is impossible
either to prove or to disprove the existence of God intellectually, but it is
helpful to have a rational faith in God as a moral Governor who will reward us
in a future life in proportion to our worthiness, our conformity, that is, to
the moral law. But we must not think of God as a Law-giver or of the moral law
as determined by God's will. Obedience to such a law, Kant maintained, would not
be true worthiness. It would be heteronomy, obedience to the law of another. In
order to be truly free and worthy, Kant insisted, a man must be his own
law-giver. He must be autonomous. He must obey only the moral law which his own
reason supplies, the categorical imperative which orders him to behave as he
would wish everyone in the whole universe to behave. "Act as though the maxim of
your action were by your will to become a universal law of nature." We must obey
this categorical imperative for duty's sake alone, not from any other motive,
not even out of regard for God.
In his Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone (1793) Kant attempted "to
discover in Scripture that sense which harmonizes with the holiest teaching of
reason," (57) that is, with his own philosophy. According to Kant, Adam's sin is
an allegory which symbolizes our failure to obey the categorical imperative for
duty's sake alone. Regeneration is the resolve to give this imperative the
required single-minded obedience. Satan represents the evil principle in human
nature. The Son of God is a personification of the good principle. The kingdom
of God is "an ethical commonwealth." It will come on earth when the transition
is made from an "ecclesiastical faith to the universal religion of reason."
(d) The Philosophy of History—Georg W. F. Hegel
Georg W. F. Hegel (1770-1831 ) developed his philosophy of history as an
alternative to the critical philosophy of Immanuel Kant. (58) More clearly than
most subsequent thinkers Hegel discerned the basic fallacy in Kant's approach to
the knowledge question. Kant's critical philosophy, Hegel observed, was an
attempt "to know before we know." (59) In other words, Kant tried to isolate the
human mind from the rest of reality and analyze it all by itself. This, Hegel
pointed out, is a mistake. We can know nothing certain about the human mind
unless we know something certain about the whole of reality, of which the human
mind is but a part. We can not know a part until we know the whole.
Instead, however, of receiving by faith God's revelation of Himself in nature,
in the Scriptures, and in the Gospel of Christ and finding in this revelation
the necessary universal knowledge, Hegel turned his back on the orthodox
Christian faith and sought the solution of his problem in a pantheism similar to
that of Spinoza. Philosophy, Hegel maintained, must be a system. "Unless it is a
system a philosophy is not a scientific production." (60) At the center of
Hegel's philosophic system is the Idea. This Idea is the Absolute. It is not
logically dependent on any other idea, but all other ideas are logically
dependent on it. Hence the Idea is the logical ground, or explanation, of the
universe.
According to Hegel, philosophy is divided into three parts. "I. Logic: the
science of the Idea in and for itself. II. The Philosophy of Nature: the science
of the Idea in its otherness. III. The Philosophy of Spirit: the science of the
Idea come back to itself out of that otherness.'' (61) The reason for this
three-fold division of philosophy was Hegel's belief that the universe is
constantly engaged in a threefold process which Hegel called Dialectic (a Greek
philosophical term signifying the discovery of truth through discussion). Logic
is continually converting itself into Nature (the material world) and then
returning to itself as Spirit. Thesis (affirmation) is always transforming
itself into antithesis (negation) and then coming back as synthesis (a
combination of the two). Hence, according to Hegel it is "narrow" and "dogmatic"
to assume that of two opposite assertions the one must be true and the other
false. We ought rather to recognize, Hegel insisted, that in such cases both
propositions contain elements of higher truth.
Hegel regarded human history as the third phase of the universal process
(Dialectic). Human history is the Idea returning to itself as Spirit It is
Spirit seeking to know itself. According to Hegel, the essence of Spirit is
freedom. Hence freedom is the theme of human history. History, Hegel taught, is
divided into three periods. First, the period of the ancient, oriental nations
who were governed by despots and knew only that one (the despot) was free.
Second, the period of the Greeks and Romans who were free themselves but kept
slaves and so knew only that some are free. Finally, there is the period of the
Germanic nations, who live under constitutional monarchies and know that all men
are free. For Hegel freedom was inseparably connected with the State and reached
its most perfect form under a constitutional monarchy. "The State is the Divine
Idea as it exists on earth." (62)
(e) Philosophy Since Hegel—Neo-Kantianism. Existentialism
During the latter part of the nineteenth century there was a trend away from
Hegelianism back to the philosophy of Kant and his completely untenable position
that it is possible to know something certain about a part of reality without
knowing anything certain about reality as a whole. Various schools of
Neo-Kantians adopted distinctive attitudes toward this fundamental problems.
(63) At Marburg they attempted to solve it by denying that there is any reality
outside of human experience. At Heidelberg they ignored it, concentrating rather
on Kant's doctrine of the will and the categorical imperative. At Goettingen A.
Ritschl and his followers pursued a similar course in the theological field.
"Theology without metaphysics," was their slogan. God is love and only love. It
was in this sense that the Ritschlians called God Father. Christ they conceived
of as the Founder of the Kingdom of God, the ethical commonwealth described by
Immanuel Kant. They regarded Him as God, but not really. Only in the sense that
for them He had "the value" of God. (64) This Ritschlianism was preached
vigorously in the United States by Walter Rauschenbusch (1861-1918) under the
title of "the social Gospel" and became the quasi-official theology of the
Federal Council of Churches. (65) As such it was a factor in the socialistic
legislation of the New Deal era.
Existentialism is a philosophical movement begun in Denmark by Soren Kierkegaard
(1813-1855). Kierkegaard's leading thought was that the different possible
conceptions of life are so sharply at variance with each other that we must
choose between them. Hence his catchword either/or. (66) Moreover, each
particular person must make this choice for himself. Hence his second catchword
the individual. Life is always pressing on and forever leading to new
possibilities and new decisions. Hence we ever stand before the unknown. We
cannot be sure that the future will resemble the past. Hence a logically
connected philosophy such as Hegel's is impossible. Our choices must be made by
jerks and leaps. Only thus, Kierkegaard insisted, will we do justice to our
individual existences. (67)
Existentialism was revived after World War I by Jaspers (1883-1969) (68) and
Heidegger (born 1889) (69) and popularized after World War II by Sartre (born
1905). (70) Like Kierkegaard, these philosophers emphasized the individual life
situation of each human being and its possibilities, the necessity of choosing
between these possibilities, the background of death and nothingness and the
accompanying dread and nausea, the choice itself and the freedom obtained by
this act of will. These factors they regarded as the necessary components of
authentic existence. In the theological field the leading existentialist was
Karl Barth (1886-1968) who equated the experience of existential choice with the
Christian doctrine of revelation. It is, he maintained an encounter with the
hidden God. (71)
|